Responsible mathematics and metaphors of semantics
An exposition of a philosophical argument about how words connect with their meanings, and a tentative connection to work done at Topos.
1 Introduction
Our arguments often get roadblocked when two people want to use the same word differently: often these are value-laden words like ‘good’, ‘fair’, ‘reasonable’, or ‘trustworthy’. Sometimes, surprisingly, these contentious words seem more concrete: ‘female’, ‘insurrection’, ‘alive’. Many are in between: ‘bigoted’, ‘scientific’, ‘violence’, ‘trauma’. In ordinary life, we rarely worry about this problem because we surround ourselves with others who use ordinary words in the same way we do. But in self-reflective or argumentative moments, where we wonder what some word actually means / what could be a good justification for picking one meaning over another, we can benefit from having thought more generally about meanings.
In the literature, there are many accounts of how to think of semantics, i.e. the task of understanding the meanings of our utterances: how what we say is related to what we’re talking about.1 In this post, I’ll try to summarize “A Hegelian Model of Legal Concept Determination”(Brandom 2013), which argues our default ways of thinking about semantics can be improved.2 The sorts of behavioral changes downstream of the new attitude are congenial with the Topos Institute’s mission.
2 Traditional semantics
2.1 Rule following
Traditionally, the paradigm relationships between words and their meanings are 1.) definitions or 2.) reference (to things in the world). To understand these, we first need to discuss rule-following because, whatever meanings are, they at least determine the rules for using words.
2.1.1 Obedience metaphor for rule following
There are two roles in this metaphor: the ruler and the subordinate. The subordinate makes a performance, the ruler judges whether or not it was in accord with the rule; this is what it means to follow the rule.
- I might make up a new word. What does it mean for others to use it correctly? We look to me: I have the authority to judge whether they are using it correctly.
- What it means to follow legal rules involves looking to the judgments of a chain of authority figures (judges, appellate courts, Supreme Court). For some religions, what it means to follow religious rules is similar (e.g. one’s priest, the Pope, God).
- What I mean when I use the word ‘zinc’ is determined by credentialed chemists. I can’t point to brass and say “This is zinc.”, only to respond to a disagreeing chemist with “Well, that’s not what I mean by ‘zinc’.” Likewise, what I mean by “2+2” gets determined by credentialed mathematicians.
If the above examples seem off to you, it may be because the Enlightenment modified this metaphor: societally, we stopped seeing authority figures as authoritative merely due to their place in the natural order and instead adopted a more democratic attitude. The authority of being a ruler ought be a rational authority (this is the only kind we ought submit to); this is when authority comes with a correlated kind of responsibility: to give reasons for any judgment when asked by the subordinate.
- Even if I make up a word, I’m obliged to provide a definition that we can all equally look to in order to decide whether one uses the word correctly. It becomes possible that I misuse the very word that I invented.
- There is a responsibility for legal / religious authorities to justify their judgments by appealing to legal code / scripture.
- The authority of the scientific / mathematical community comes with the responsibility to produce various forms of evidence for any claims that are made (with a high burden of proof).
2.1.2 The analytic / synthetic distinction
If you further probe the reasons behind a decision, you’ll eventually get to one of two explanations which we culturally accept as not in need of further justification. Analytic statements are “purely definitional”, such as “bachelor = unmarried man”. These are truths which we create. Synthetic statements are just facts about the world, such as a gravitational law or that there is a chair in the room. These are truths which we find.
The Enlightenment was liberating because it reduced the number of rulers whom we are not permitted to question to just two: 1.) the laws of basic logic (application of definitions) and 2.) the laws that govern the world. These are regress stoppers in conversations about meaning.
2.2 Representation: the map metaphor
It’s normal to think of our relationship to the world with the metaphor of a map representing a territory. This is a special case of the obedience metaphor: the ruler is the territory, and the subordinate is the map. To judge the correctness of the map, we must look to the territory. We take this metaphor quite seriously: the line drawn between these two different kinds of things leads to an intuitive distinction between the facts (the territory, the actual world) and our representation of it (the map, our beliefs and intentions).
2.2.1 Platitudes vs rational obligations
We talk about the difference between a substantial argument and one that is “just semantics”. We tend to view the analytic statements as platitudes / tautologies, whereas the synthetic regress stoppers are “real” and “contentful”. The former are contingent and arbitrary because we make them, the latter are obligatory for us to believe because they are fixed by the world. Before trying to improve the map metaphor, I want to acknowledge it is playing a crucial social role: if we were to naively treat all regress stoppers as if they were conventional platitudes, they would cease to be rationally-binding reasons. This is because, if it’s maps all the way down, the maps don’t provide us a reason to do anything. This is the fear that “if truth is relative, then anything goes”. So long as we are stuck with the map metaphor, it’s in our interest to uphold the distinction between facts and conventions.
3 A new metaphor
I plan to argue:
- We do have serious motivations to drop the hard distinction of analytic and synthetic statements (or facts and conventions)
- We can adopt a different metaphor for rule following and meaning that allows us to still have meaningfulness despite this radical rejection
- There are some concrete positive consequences of this change.
3.1 Reasons to drop old metaphor
The map metaphor is often appropriate to use; the problem is taking it to be the semantic model. When we hit puzzling / paradoxical / unfortunate truths, we should be open to changing the metaphor instead.
3.1.1 The Duhem point: we cannot separate meaning from beliefs
The meaning of a word is bound up in the rules for how to use it, i.e. its inferential connections to other words. However, what inferences one can make depends on all sorts of collateral beliefs one holds. Thus, we cannot first set up all of the meanings of words and, then, look at the world to see what sentences are true: we simply use language, and this fixes both what things mean and what is true. This is at odds with the firm distinction between analytic and synthetic statements.3 Of course, there was some value offered by the distinction: it’s still reasonable to call a statement analytic when the only scenarios which make us question it are ‘incredibly far-fetched’.4
Gilbert Harman makes a related point how a perceived violation of “A implies B” (i.e. an observation of A and the lack of observing B) does not tell us whether to deny the implication, deny our observation of A, or deny our lack of observing B (Harman 1986). Logic shows certain combinations of belief are incompatible but doesn’t tell us how to update our beliefs, even with perfect empirical information. This again puts pressure on the commonplace model of rationality which says we can simply look to the territory (the authority of the world, of empirical nature) to see how to adjust our map.5
3.1.2 Fuzziness of reference
Taking the map metaphor seriously means that what our expressions refer to is essential to their meaning. However, consider the phrase: “The witch who lives at the end of the street”. Suppose we don’t believe in witches; we can interpret this two ways: 1.) The speaker is referring to the woman at the end of the street and has the false belief that she is a witch, and 2.) the phrase fails to refer to her, as there do not exist any witches. But we ought feel indifferent about the significance our choice — it doesn’t seem like one the world forces us to make, and we feel either way that we grasp the meaning of the phrase.
Even non-linguistic reference is fuzzy: suppose one points at a plate. What fact of the world distinguishes this act from pointing at the color of the plate, the shape of the plate, a piece of dining ware, a plate or an elephant, a specific clump of atoms within the plate? Depending on what we are interested in, we may wish to interpret what was referred to in different ways: what, in fact, was referred to depends on us.
A final example to show why it would be worrisome if the meaning of our words was grounded by a notion of reference: we say scientists who used the plum pudding model of the electron referred to the same thing that we refer to using a wave function model. By giving these two incompatible theoretical objects the same name, we signal a kind of continuity that says “we honor these past scientists”. We don’t always do this: early experiments postulated an entity phlogiston that was released during combustion and had the interesting property of having negative mass. We could think of this as two wrong beliefs: phlogiston is in fact added during combustion, and it has a positive mass. We could take up this attitude if we chose to see the discovery of phlogiston as continuous with oxygen in the way we choose to see the negatively-charged plum as continuous with the negatively-charged probability-cloud.
3.2 Common law metaphor
Legal verdicts force us to confront the ambiguity of language. Statute law is a written body of rules created by elected officials, whereas common law is a set of unwritten principles based on judicial decisions and precedent. Statute law seems better insofar as we want delivered verdicts to come with clear reasons, such as pointing to a statute. However, we need a rules to appeal to when interpreting the concepts involved in the statute, and this leads to an infinite regress. Common law is fundamental then because it is how we stop the regress in practice.
3.2.1 The actual process of settling legal meanings
To unpack an undefined legal concept (such as “reasonable”, “malice”, “liability”), a common law judge must make a rational reconstruction of the tradition of prior judges’ interpretations of the concept. This involves picking which past interpretations were precedential (i.e. progressive, good). I illustrate this below with judges over time arranged via the horizontal axis, the precedential judges colored in green, and we (the present judge) are colored in black on the right.
The judge may not make this partition arbitrarily: a rational reconstruction is a kind of making that is also a finding. It’s clearly the kind of creative act we would call ‘making’, but it is also ‘finding’ because the verdict cannot be presented as an arbitrary choice; we must tell a story where we find out which verdicts are precedential according to our understanding of what the problematic concept actually means. To put this another way, rational reconstructions give contingency the form of necessity.
- Necessity: Whether past judges explicitly realized it or not, their decisions were the result of (objective) norms which have always existed. (We must understand “reasonable”, “malice”, “liability” as having actual / objective norms governing their usage).
- Contingency: Maybe my biases or what I ate for breakfast did in fact influence my reconstruction. That’s for future judges to decide. In fact, rather than thinking of us as the judge at the far right, we should think of ourselves as somewhere in the middle:
Each judge in the past has themselves made such a retrospective, rational reconstruction of the meaning of the problematic concept. It is their very own reconstruction that is being judged as precedential or not in the present judge’s reconstruction.
The present verdict will have a lasting impact only insofar as future judges look back and see this reconstruction as a good one. So the authority structure is not one-directional like the obedience metaphor: past judges are authoritative over the present judge because the present judge can only appeal to previous judges in constructing a verdict. However, the present judge has authority over the past judges by regarding some as precedential but not others. Likewise, we have the same pair of relationships (but reversed) to our present and future peers.
While this is not a metaphor in the context of our society working out the semantic content of legal terms, we can start to use this model as a metaphor to understand semantics generally. In our ordinary conversations or in professional contexts, should we be challenged in our usage of concepts like free will, electron, cat, plus, Aristotle, etc., we respond by effectively providing a rational reconstruction that justifies how our usage is in accord with what the concept means (formulated as an explicit rule) at the same time showing how this explicit rule lets us make sense of past usage (both past usage in accord with the rule and the mistakes made in the past). Whether or not we actually were meaningfully using the concept depends on whether our justifications are found precedential by present and future peers. This means saying electron, cat, plus, Aristotle, refer to “different kinds of things” can be understood as saying that the legal traditions which govern their use are very different types of social structures.
3.2.2 An amendment to the Enlightenment’s amendment
I described the Enlightenment amendment to the traditional obedience metaphor as saying there was a certain responsibility that rational authority must take on: to give reasons. In the spirit of that, this metaphor simply describes in more detail the kinds of reasons one ought give (i.e. give a rational reconstruction of the history of the rule).
The obedience metaphor no longer has judge and accused; it is now judge and judge. This is even more radically democratic than the amendment which continued the model of authority and subjugation (so long as the subjugation was in accord with universal principles, like natural law and the laws of logic). This lets us see the previous amendment as progressive but incomplete.6
3.3 Consequences
A radical consequence of these considerations is that the two regress stoppers, “Logic” and “Reality”, are deprived of their unquestionable authority. Nevertheless we are able to ground authority by the democratic, social process of the common law metaphor. I conclude by very briefly highlighting my personal feeling of how this pertains to Topos.
3.3.3 Category theory as paradigm case of rational reconstructions
Category theorists are familiar with the technique of challenging paradigms that explain things based on their inherent nature and replacing them with paradigms that explain things due to how they are intertwined with related things. The move made in this post is no different: we learn how to stop appealing to how things “actually are” as a final explainer.
The general move category theorists make is, e.g., “You say you understand what you are doing by taking a product of two numbers. You would be better off to stop thinking of ‘product’ as that specific thing and instead think of it as this abstract universal property. It corresponds to what-you-were-calling ‘product’ in this particular context but also generalizes very nicely to other contexts you where you’d say ‘product’.” This is making a rational reconstruction of the history of “product”. Some past uses may not fit the mold, and you must apologize and say those are not precedential.
Category theory gives contingency (there are unlimited different ways to make an abstraction which encompasses most historical uses of the word product; category theorists have chosen one) the form of necessity (we interpret others as actually using the categorical product, even if they don’t realize it)9, and we accept that future mathematicians may find an even better abstraction which further improves the concept of a product, trusting that they would only do it if they saw this change as further illuminating what we were trying to do by making (or finding) the categorical product.
An essential component of rational reconstructions (which keeps the metaphor from slipping into postmodern meaninglessness) is that the judge must not make this partition arbitrarily: the partition of the tradition into precedential and non-precedential rulings must be framed as the gradual revealing of something universal, which is entirely in line with the category-theoretic analogue.
References
Footnotes
Two relevant Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy pages: Theories of meaning and Normativity of meaning↩︎
I also draw from Richard Rorty in (Rorty 1989) and (Rorty 1996).↩︎
Let’s test this: there should be some experiences that would make us challenge statements which seem definitionally true. E.g. “cats are mammals”: this is crazy-but-possible, suppose future scientists look closer at the underlying matter of cats and discover they are secretly made up of nanobots which only appear to be biological given the limitations of our current technology.↩︎
The paradigm case where it’s appropriate to use a two-phase separation is with artificial languages (where it feels like we can assign a semantics to the elements of the language piece-by-piece). Again this is not different in kind from the cat example: it’s just that the kinds of experiences we would need in order to want to change our chosen foundations of math and logic are quite radical.↩︎
Bayesianism does not solve this problem: it merely quantifies “deny the implication” (“lower the credence”) and adds a fourth option we are free to choose from, which is to rethink whether we chose a sensible prior.↩︎
As a meta point: in order to be consistent with the common law metaphor, I was obliged to spend so many words going into historical detail about the old metaphor so that I can paint a picture of the new metaphor as a friendly amendment to the old one; that is essential to this post being about meaning, i.e. hooking onto the actual concept of meaning, as opposed to merely being a bunch of definitions connected to my idiosyncratic use of the word “meaning”.↩︎
“Oh, you must not think this cat-nanobot scenario is as far-fetched as I thought it was…”↩︎
Caveat: it still may be a very hard task, practically, and the old way of talking is appropriate for this limiting case. But the lesson of this post is to see this as an extreme case on some spectrum, rather than a difference in kind.↩︎
We can imagine a possible world where everyone is applying category theory even though no one ever thought or talked about it. This is an important demonstration that we are not naively “reducing everything to language games”.↩︎